The Burden of Proof.
On the impossibility of technology assessment for the
Human Genome Project
MICHAEL DRIESCHNER, BOCHUM
The editors asked me to elaborate a bit on a point I made during the conference at
a panel discussion, namely on the complexity of natural processes and the warn-
ing it gives us, not to tinker about with it: If it were not for other reasons then for
the one reason that we cannot assess the consequences.
Actually my point of view is no different from what any reader of newspapers
could think of. I feel encouraged to publish this view in the present conference
volume because of my special experience with this kind of questions from my
time in the "Max-Planck-Institut zur Erforschung der Lebensbedingungen der
wissenschaftlich-technischen Welt", where in the course of interdisciplinary re-
search and philosophical considerations (and, correspondingly, much disappoint-
ment about its possibilities) many problems of this kind were discussed.—So,
what is at issue?
We are enjoying progress. On average we reach twice the age of our ancestors.
Nobody has to go hungry. Practically all of the 80 million dense population of
Germany live in affluence, most of them rather struggle with their overweight. We
can reach every location on earth physically within 24 hours. Informationally we
can even be anywhere within fractions of a second, if somebody is there with a
cellular phone.
We can determine over ourselves to an extent unthinkable still a few hundred
years ago, from the election of the president to worker participation, form free
choice of partners and trade to free choice of the number of children. We are even
promised that in the near future we shall be able to determine the quality of our
children, or at least that only those will be born who are free from handicaps. It
should be like paradise. Only people do not seem to be happier or more satisfied
now. Is it possible that happiness does not depend on this kind of changes?
In the late 60s we could have learnt a historical lesson from a coincidence: The
Hudson Institute, Herman Kahn's "think tank", published a book "The year 2000"
(Kahn and Wiener 1967), an enthusiastic picture of the land of milk and honey we
1
stand on the threshold of, where all problems that harass us will be solved.—In
the very same year there came up the discussion about problems of the environ-
ment and of the Third World. At that time we still mainly spoke of traffic noise
and starvation in the colonies (Heinrichs 1968). In the meantime the discussion
has broadened, and we see that we are well on our way of making the world unin-
habitable for our descendants if we continue to live as we do now. Beyond that,
our way of life is such that only a small fraction of humanity can participate in it
(Meadows 1972).
Thus instead of Cockaigne we had suddenly the Apocalyptic Riders. What had
happened? Don't we have everything under control, as we thought?
Let us have a look at a case that is far from genetic engineering, that we already
overlook, though, historically for some time: The automobile! When Mr. Benz
built his first motor carriage the technology assessment of that time could have
emphasized the saving of space for horse stables, the advantage that the motor
carriage would not cost anything when it does not ride, and the higher velocity of
travel. Traffic victims, the problems of parking, cities adapted to the automobile,
splashing into the open countryside, monoculture of department stores in the inner
cities, the dependence of Germany's entire economy on the automobile: The very
best technology assessment could not have foreseen all that!
Individual traffic is still a limited, relatively small field, open before our eyes, that
has got its heavy impact on life only by the development of the automobile. But I
think I can show in this field what my concern is: That for the questions of tech-
nology assessment it is all important to look up from what is immediately before
one's eyes and to gain an entirely new perspective.
It is interesting to see that we seem to have so much less time today than in stage-
coach times (when people of our status had to walk, anyway). Did it not seem self
evident that we would save time when we rode faster, taking less time for the
same distance?—I know two quite different approaches to explaining this discrep-
ancy. Both are rather schematic. But both have a quality that seems necessary:
they help look up from the workpiece right before my eyes.
The first one is IVAN ILLICH's quite serious calculation that by car one is really
even slower than walking or on bicycle. This comes out because he does not only
calculate the time immediately needed for the ride, but also the time necessary in
2
advance for being able to ride: Time for car administration and repair; and mainly
time to earn the money that driving a car costs.
Let us take a rather realistic example: Somebody goes 1000 km by his car per
month, at an average speed of 50 km/h. This costs about 600 DM per month, ac-
cording to the table of the German automobile association ADAC. Let us take the
net wage of an average worker being 15 DM per hour. It takes him 20 hours for
plainly driving 1000 km, but for earning the necessary money it takes this average
worker another 40 hours. So actually it takes him 60 hours for 1000 km, which
results in an average speed of 16 km/h. You go that fast on bicycle as well! In re-
ality nobody would go 1000 km every month if he had not that easy and seem-
ingly swift method to do so by car. On foot he would maybe go 100 km per month
and take for that distance, very roughly, 20 hours. Now he prefers a car: If he
wants to have a car ready at hand, even if he does not use it, he would have to
spend the equivalent of 20 hours of work. In order to cover 100 km "quickly" he
would use another 2 hours. So on the whole he would spend 22 hours to cover 100
km: A human being living the way of life of stagecoach times could not save time
by using a car, but it would take him extra time!
An entirely different model is used by CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSÄCKER in order
to make understandable the shortage of time of our contemporaries. Maybe this
model is as valid as IVAN ILLICH's. WEIZSÄCKER gives the following calculation:
Let us assume that I go to see friends or visit events that are within an hour of my
home (or whatever time you choose; for our calculation this does not matter). I
assume for simplicity that such opportunities are distributed uniformly around my
home. Then the number of opportunities I can reach easily is proportional to the
surface I could cover within an hour. When I walk, that surface is a circle with
radius 5 km. When I drive it is a circle with radius 50 km, that is with a surface
one hundred times as large. Thus a driver has about one hundred times as many
opportunities he could or might want to visit as a pedestrian.—No wonder he runs
short of time!
Those calculations may serve as examples for an unconventional widening of our
view. At the same time they may illustrate that technology assessment depends
largely on our imagination: If there is a possibility we have not thought of, but
which is crucial, our whole technology assessment is useless.
3
Let us return to the consequences of technical interventions into our lives: They
are much more complicated than transportation! Already the climate on earth is so
complex a structure that we have striven in vain for many decades to predict the
consequences of the increase of CO2 in the air. How much more this must be valid
for the extremely complex interrelations within a human organism or human soci-
ety! An intervention as simple as the introduction of "the pill"—how much has it
revolutionized not only the relations between sexes, but our whole way of life. Or
take the phone: materially entirely harmless, barely noticeable; but it has turned
our entire social structure upside down!
So now we go ahead and start assembling our offspring from blueprint. That un-
fortunate debate about "the certificate" ("Schein") of the last months had one
merit, though: it brought into public awareness once again that abortion could be a
problem. Whoever thinks about it at all in Germany, as, for example, the col-
leagues from the medical ethics department, mostly sees the issue—that seems
self-evident!—only under the aspect of self determination of the parents: To the
same extent as my profession or my consumption is at my disposal, I should be
able, as far as technically possible, to determine the quality of my offspring. The
next step of technical progress seems to be within our scope: Just now TV news
report that the first human chromosome has been sequenced completely; the rest
of the human genome will probably follow shortly. Nobody knows up to now
what we can do with this knowledge. But certainly a technical application will be
found, just as in the cases of all scientific innovations until now: There was al-
ways a (profitable!) application at hand! Think only of the technology of in vitro
fertilization—it was the one invention that made the misfortune of a childless
couple a real tragedy in that it promised a technically realizable remedy.
In the meantime we have become prudent; we think: "We have learnt that every
new technology was charged with side effects we had not imagined when it was
introduced. Thus we are doing technology assessment to gain control over this
problem. Unfortunately this does not work yet one hundred percent satisfactorily,
we are still at the beginning. So we shall have to do massive technology assess-
ment research!"—Has anybody ever considered that this beats everything in hu-
man hubris, over-estimating human abilities? As if it were ever possible to "gain
control over" the consequences of human action, beyond the very immediate ones!
4
If we have learnt anything at all from genome research of the last decades, it is
this: The structure of the genome is extremely more complex than we had ever
imagined beforehand. Any progress in this research brings to light new complica-
tions, every glance around a new corner opens our view at a whole new scenery of
streets and squares of a complexity inconceivable before. Structurally one could
have imagined something like that from the beginning. But what kind of complex-
ity this really would be, nobody could have guessed beforehand. Still much less
anyone is capable of guessing the consequences of technical interventions in sys-
tems that are so complex.
Certainly it is conceivable that we might find interventions that have a very nar-
row positive effect, for example cure a certain hereditary disease. But even there
we should ask if such intervention makes sense. Take the example of a hereditary
disease: There are even today good ways to prevent the birth of handicapped chil-
dren, in that parents who are in danger to have offspring with hereditary diseases
would not have offspring at all. There are many, in their majority worse reasons
for which couples decide not to have children, so why not for the reason that those
children might be handicapped?—We have learnt from this well-known method of
preventing hereditary diseases, which abyss can open behind "pure technique", in
this case the whole complex of eugenics. This turns out true even for methods the
technique of which is simple and the consequences foreseeable. How much more
this must be true of a so far unknown technology, even if our first impression is
simple and harmless as well. Thus the best requirement for the introduction of a
new technology would be the proof, according to the strongest criteria, that its ap-
plication is harmless.
This requirement is recognized even today as valid, but, alas!, rather according to
the guideline: "If nobody can think of anything that can be harmful with that tech-
nology, we can regard it as harmless."—The criterion should rather be the other
way around, that the one who proposes a new technology is obliged to show that
he has checked all (really all!) possibilities, and has found that none is harmful,
including "social" consequences, as in the case of the eugenics debate.
One can easily see that nobody will be able to do that, regardless of the type of
technology. That means that we should not start at all tinkering with the genome!
We started with examples from transportation and other "simple" technologies.
For those, in principle, the same considerations apply. But would not the whole of
5
society come to a stand-still if we stuck to the advice not to tinker with complex
systems?
What do those stories with cars and blueprints aim at?—They are supposed to
open up a view that is not given automatically with considering technological
problems, that is not included in "technology assessment". The examples should
verify my conclusion:
There might be cases where the harvest for humanity from a technology is obvi-
ous. Take, for instance, the necessity to check cholera: Sewage had to be con-
structed, and nobody gave long considerations about the question whether sewage
could be harmful. But sewage was a technology well tried and tested from Roman
times on.—When it came to carrying through smallpox vaccination one had to
weigh up the consequences of an epidemic against the consequences of vaccina-
tion. It was a forced decision under conditions of ignorance—as it is necessarily in
almost all practical cases.
But:
In the case of genetic engineering the problem is that we know, on the one hand,
so little about the very complex systems involved, such that technology assess-
ment is practically impossible; and that, on the other hand, the consequences of
not applying genetic engineering are obviously harmless.—This is probably an
unorthodox view; because it is rather easy to draw a line from any scientific
method or scientific result whatsoever to consequences that are, if not salvation of
mankind, at least a decisive improvement of its fate. To prove that it suffices to
read at random some last paragraphs from papers in, say, Scientific American!—
Such claims are rather easily unmasked as public relations talk. If one gives it a
closer look one can see, in general, that there is no harm in keeping away from the
proposal. And one can see as easily that nobody can in the least imagine what the
consequences of realizing the proposal would be for the very complex system at
stake.
It is so easy—with one false move within the almost absolute power of our tech-
nical means—to destroy what cannot be reconstructed within centuries!
To weigh soberly in such discussions, not to let oneself seduce by arguments of
"technical sweetness": Such are the needs of the moment.
6
Reference:
Heinrichs J (1968) Welternährungskrise oder: Ist eine Hungerkatastrophe unausweichlich?
Rowohlt, Reinbek
Kahn H, Wiener A (1967) The year 2000; a framework for speculation on the next thirty-three
years. Macmillan New York
Meadows D (1972) The M.I.T.-Club of Rome Project on the Predicament of Mankind. M.I.T
Press, Cambridge, Mass.
7